Situational Love & a Postmodern Ethic
People make decisions everyday about how they are going to act,
what they are going to say, and what they are going to do. But
how do people make these decisions? What guides people to choose
to act one way over another? One thing that helps people make
decisions is their ethics. In this paper, I will outline my personal
communication ethic, as inspired by the writings of Joseph Fletcher
and Martha Cooper. After summarizing their research, I will propose
my own code of ethics.
Joseph Fletcher proposes a situational ethic with a guiding universal
principle of love (Fletcher, 1966). He believes that no act is
intrinsically good or evil, but instead "good and evil are
extrinsic to the action" (Fletcher, 1966, p. 59). For example,
one could not say that murder is intrinsically evil, because there
are circumstances when murder would be acceptable, as in self-defense.
The act of killing someone is not evil in and of itself, instead
the evil of the act is found in the situation.
The overarching guiding principle of his situational ethic is
agape love, which is defined as "Christian love" or
a "giving love" that is "non-reciprocal" and
"neighbor-regarding" (Fletcher, 1966, p. 79). Christian
love is distinguished from friendship love (Phila) and romantic
love (Eros), because it is not an emotion, but a "will, disposition,
it is an attitude, not a feeling" (Fletcher, 1966, p. 79).
Although written laws aim to promote good, Fletcher points out
that sometimes laws force you to act contrary to love (Fletcher,
1966). He does not want people to "be hypnotized by some
abstract law" and follow without thinking, but to take time
to analyze the gray areas of morality that the law cannot account
for (Fletcher, 1966, p. 65). He says:
"Having set out laws based on ethical absolutes and universals,
love compels them to make more and more rules with which to break
the rules. This is the ridiculous result when law ethics (as
in the Christian tradition) tries to keep control, yet want to
pay homage to love" (Fletcher, 1996, p. 67).
Lawmakers are caught in a difficult situation because of the
constant fluctuation between asserting universals and making exceptions
to those rules. Fletcher does not believe that laws are useless,
but acknowledges that there is a major problem with them because
they do not distinguish between situations. Consequently, the
situationist should move beyond the law and hold "that whatever
is the most loving thing in the situation is the right and good
thing" (Fletcher, 1966, p. 65). Again, the type of love
he refers to is the agape or Christian love.
In some ways, leaving moral judgments to the situationist is
risky because "situation ethics aim to widen freedom"
(Fletcher, 1966, p. 84). However, with that freedom comes the
responsibility to be "as well-informed and reasonable as
[one] is capable of being," (Fletcher, 1966, p. 10). Another
important tool for the situationist is the "ethical maxims
of his [or her] community and its heritage" (Fletcher, 1966,
p.26). A person should know the tradition and heritage of his/her
community, but be willing to "compromise them or set them
aside in the situation if love seems better served by doing so"
(Fletcher, 1966, p. 26). In summary, the situationist should
seek to be reasonable and well informed about the heritage of
the community, before making a decision.
Although she wrote many years after Fletcher, Martha Cooper deals
with similar problems of absolutes in postmodern thinking (Cooper
as excerpted in Johannesen, 2002). Postmoderninty "poses
a challenge because the very grounds for judgment seems to have
split apart beneath those who would judge" (Cooper as excerpted
in Johannesen, 2002, p. 300). Instead of accepting universal
truths, postmodernity "is the recognition of multiple perspectives,"
which poses a problem for the issue of judgment (Cooper as excerpted
in Johannesen, 2002, p. 313). Coopers solution is to "decenter"
or "suspend" judgment through an ethic of care and an
ethic of resistance (Cooper as excerpted in Johannesen, 2002,
p. 302). She describes the ethic of discourse, which encourages
questioning and deliberation and leads to judgment, but says,
"making judgments is not the only route to ethical behavior
in a postmodern world" (Cooper as excerpted in Johannesen,
2002, p. 313). The ethic of care encourages responding, empathizing
with another's story, and identifying with that person, all without
judging (Cooper as excerpted in Johannesen, 2002). Furthermore,
the ethic of resistance encourages affirmation, empowerment, and
tolerance through ritual celebration (Cooper as excerpted in Johannesen,
2002).
Postmodernity implies a "value for perspectives other than
our own, especially perspectives that are marginalized" (Cooper
as excerpted in Johannesen, 2002, p. 314). Although valuing all
perspectives can cause problems when trying to determine right
and wrong, it is important to recognize that there are many viewpoints
that are not heard. Her three ethics are all ways one can respond
to the call of the Other. She believes that every person has
"an ethical, or moral impulse
that occurs when the voice
of an Other who is experiencing the repressive effects of power
is heard" (Cooper as excerpted in Johannesen, 2002, p. 302-303).
Through her work, Cooper attempts to recuperate ground for judgment
in the difficult world of postmodernism, through her three part
ethic.
Taking into account the writings of Cooper and Fletcher, I propose
my own code of ethics. I will point out the strengths and weaknesses
of their ethics in an attempt to define my own. I think Fletcher's
situation ethic is important because it allows room for all the
gray areas in morality. He acknowledges that there are situations
in which laws cannot give you guidance. In those circumstances,
you must turn to your own judgment of the situation and figure
out what is most loving. I agree with most of what Fletcher says,
but see two weaknesses. First, I think he puts too much value
on peoples' own ability to determine what is most loving in a
situation. Although he says they should arm themselves with as
much knowledge as they can, I can see many areas where the test
of "agape" love would not be clear. Furthermore, people
have vastly different ideas of what it means to show loving concern.
The second weakness I see is that he assumes a Christian perspective.
Although this is helpful for finding examples of agape love (as
in Christ), he leaves many people out of his ethic.
For Cooper, I like that the postmodern ethic values multiple
perspectives. It is important for people to recognize where they
get their ideas. I also think her ethic of care is important
because "questioning every background assumption is a luxury
rarely afforded oppressed people" (Cooper, as excerpted in
Johannesen, 2002, p 305). The ethic of care requires "little
in the way of elite resources, but involving specific skills"
(Cooper, as excerpted in Johannesen, 2002, p. 306) so that even
oppressed people can practice it. I also like her emphasis on
hearing the call of the "other," because it places importance
on going outside yourself to help another person and does not
leave ethics at the personal, individual level. As far as the
issue of relativism in postmodernism, I feel Cooper bends over
backwards to find ways around judgment. I would like to propose
another way of looking at relativism that does not nullify judgment.
Stanley Fish wrote an article entitled Condemnation without Absolutes,
that addresses the issue of absolute moralities within the emerging
postmodern belief that "maintains that there can be no independent
standard for determining which of many rival interpretations of
an event is the true on" (Fish, 2003, p. A19). When asked
if the events of September 11 meant an end to postmodern relativism,
he responded by first defining relativism and then explaining
why it is not ending (Fish, 2003). Relativism does not mean that
you "are unable to prefer your own convictions to that of
your adversary" because he says, "our convictions are
by definition preferred" (Fish, 2001). He defines relativism
as:
"The practice of putting yourself in your adversary's shoes,
not in order to wear them as your own but in order to have some
understanding (far short of approval) of why someone else might
want to wear them" (Fish, 2001, p.1).
He believes this type of relativism is just another name
for "serious thought" and should continue. The important
distinction that Fish makes is that just because you recognize
others' perspectives does not mean you have to do away with your
own convictions in judgments. I prefer Fish's response to relativism,
rather than Cooper's, who tries to find ways around judging.
My Code of Ethics
Having examined Fletcher, Cooper, and Fish, I would like to propose
my own ethic, using the language of the narrative (Fisher, as
cited in Griffin, 1997). Instead of looking at ethics as situational,
the situations should be viewed as occurring within a story, not
as an isolated event. In reality, the way people act and react
in situations results from many things, including their view of
the world. The narrative, or story about the world, will determine
what the most loving thing is to do in a situation. For example,
by the worldview of Americans, we see the issue of female genital
mutilation as horrific and undeniably wrong. However, within
the narrative of the communities that practice it, the overarching
belief may be that women need to be controlled. Therefore, their
practices seem justified and right within their story of the world.
With that in mind, here are the six points of my ethical code.
· Come to every situation with an open mind, making sure
you are aware of your own beliefs and narrative of the world.
You choose to be part of a community (i.e. religious, professional,
etc.) and often this community helps define your view of the world.
Make sure you understand your own dispositions.
· You should analyze each situation to figure out what
is the most loving thing to do. Your definition of love will
depend upon your own beliefs and your own narrative. It is vitally
important that you consult other wise people in your community
to gain insight from the past.
· Seek multiple perspectives (from people of different
narratives) on situations or issues in order to gain more insight
into your own beliefs.
· Be sensitive to the call of the Other and follow your
own moral impulse to respond to that person in the best way you
know how.
· Remember the ethic of care is another way to respond
to situations if you do not feel that discourse is appropriate.
· Treat people with love, valuing them as people, even
if you do not agree with them.
In conclusion, I used the writings of Fletcher and Cooper to
help me form my personal (not professional) ethical code. In
combining a situational ethic with a postmodern value for multiple
perspectives, as well as a recognition of moral relativism, I
feel that I have come up with a more complete way to view the
world.
References
Cooper, M. (2002). Decentering Judgment: Toward a Postmodern
Communication Ethic. In R. Johannesen, Ethics in Human Communication
(pp.299-314). Prospect Heights: Waveland Press, Inc.
Fletcher, J. (1966). Situation Ethics: The New Morality. Philadelphia: Westminster Press.
Fletcher, J. & Wassmer, T. (1970). Hello, Lovers! An Introduction to Situation Ethics. Washington/Cleveland: Corpus Books.
Fish, S. (2001, October 21). Condemnation without Absolutes.
The New York Times, pp. A19.
Griffin, E. (1997). An introduction to communication theory. New
York: Mc Graw Hill.