VII
The next
aspect of moral responsibility for health we are likely to forget is the
affective component in moral conviction. Judgments of the moral
"ought," what I as a Christian should do or
avoid, and action upon such
conclusions, originate not simply in rational analysis, book learning, or
exposure to sociological fact. They have deep roots in our sensitivities and
emotions. This has particular relevance where the health needs of the elderly
and dependent (fetuses, infants, retarded, the poor) are concerned.
What I
mean to suggest here is the difficulty we experience in a media culture in
remaining sensitive to human hurt, deprivation, and injustice. The efficiency
of the media means that human suffering and loneliness are dished up to us both
frequently and mediately. By "mediately" I mean that we learn of the
sickness, suffering, starving, death, and isolation of others several levels removed
from the happening--often enough in a cozy chair with a glass of standard swank
Beefeaters ready to soften any overly severe blows and to soothe our quivering
ganglia. Thus the body counts in Vietnam night after night had inevitably the
effect of chipping away at our moral horror at what was happening. Being
surrounded by sickness, pain, and death, we get hardened to it. The phenomenon
has been noted in nurses frequently. I speak as an American when I say that in
far too many areas it is true to say that "the feeling has gone out of
it." "Oh just another rape" is a phrase that, God forbid, can
become as common as a comment on the weather.
I will
pursue this for a moment, because it is utterly essential. What is so often
lacking in contemporary life is passion. For example, couples talk of
affection and tenderness and read manuals of marital gymnastics to find them.
The more they desire feeling and passion, the more it escapes them. We are the
clinicians of quality where quality escapes the mere clinician. We talk about
the poor, their terrible situation; yet we eat well, drink well. We get mad
(passionate) at injustice only when it hits us or our family. Those who get
mad when it hits others (the neighbor as the self, so to speak) are often
viewed as marginal characters.
Passion
is the beginning of any true moral responsibility and therefore of
responsibility for health. It is the inner identification with the suffering
and the downtrodden. It is that personal startup that gets us off-center a
bit-self-center-and propels us to examine our consciences, comforts, and
priorities. To develop genuine passion and concern, I believe we have to he
exposed to those who suffer. There is a qualitative difference in the approach
of those who have seen, touched, and hugged a hydrocephalic child and those who
have not. There is a qualitative difference in the concern of those who have
companied with the dying and those who only write statistics and articles about
the experience. Those who have seen some retirement homes know in a
dimensionally different way the health problems of the elderly; those who have
seen know, for example, how our society has failed to come to grips with this
problem.
Moral
responsibility for health means, far more than we have admitted in our lives
and policies, firsthand exposure to the problems of health; for without such
experience, we are likely to remain without passion-and therefore without one
of the basic ingredients of moral responsibility.
VIII
The next point to advert to in unpacking the notion
of "moral responsibility" is the cultural shaping of our grasp of
basic human values. In the first chapter I adverted to the fact that we are corporately
homo technologicus in our
attitudes. This prethematic shaping tends to affect profoundly our moral
judgments.
Something
of a highwater mark in this technological bias is reached in the writings of
Joseph Fletcher, as I note in Chapter 15.
For instance, Fletcher writes: "Man is a maker and a selector and a
designer and the more rationally contrived and deliberate anything is, the more
human it is." On this basis he
continues: "Laboratory reproduction
is radically human compared to conception by ordinary heterosexual
intercourse. It is willed, chosen, purposed, and controlled, and surely these
are among the traits that distinguish Homo sapiens
from others in the animal genus. . . .
Coital reproduction is, therefore, less human than laboratory reproduction."6
My only point here-but it is a very
serious point and one we are likely to overlook-is that responsibility for
health demands that we attend to and lift out those cultural leanings and
biases that may distort our grasp on the basic values and hence prejudice our
notion of what moral responsibility means and requires.
IX
My
final point in dealing with health and care for health is that our
responsibility must be "holistic," Otherwise it begins to suffer
erosion and is simply incredible as a form of witness to others. By holistic I
mean that responsibility must be conceived and spoken of as covering all of
those things that affect life and health. It must be part and parcel of an attitude
toward persons that defends their rights, is strongly prophetic about warfare,
about poverty, about quality of life in all aspects and at all ages. Why is
this important? Because without such a reach and universality, our own sense of
responsibility begins to erode by being selective. One cannot responsibly care
for the person-the self of others-by caring for only a single aspect of the
person.
We
know this notionally, but it is terribly hard to make it part of ourselves, to
know it evaluatively. I recall a panel I was on at Georgetown University on the
problem of abortion. Three of us participated: a pro-abortionist, a prolifer,
and I. The students were, by and large, strongly opposed to abortion, but the
language used by the prolife lawyer involved all but "turned them
off." At one point I noted that we must also be concerned with what happens
to children once they are born. We must be concerned about whether they are
starving, are beaten, are abandoned in gutters and on front steps.
"Otherwise," I argued,
"our abortion stand is selective and one-eyed." To my consternation,
the lawyer responded: "That has
nothing to do with the problem of abortion." I submit that it has
everything to do with it, with our own sense of responsibility and with our
credibility. This same tunnel vision can overtake us as we reflect on our
responsibilities for health.
These
are but some of the things we are likely to forget when discussing "man's moral responsibility for
health." I am sure there are many more. But if one details too many things
we are likely to forget, one becomes a self-fulfilling prophet and all but
guarantees our memory failure.
6Joseph
Fletcher, "Ethical Aspects of Genetic Controls," New England Journal of Medicine,
285(1971), 776.