voidably be saying
what he or she would want to be (what kind of life), not what kind of life
they could come to live with God's grace and sufficient supports were they
terribly deprived. Second, the tiny infant has no background, no history, no
biography of aspirations and perspectives against which we can make a judgment.
And third, therefore, the kind of judgment we make about defective newborns is
in principle applicable to all babies. It is generalizable. That means that all babies are at risk in
our qualityof4ife judgments about instigation or withdrawal of treatment at
this time.
On the
other hand, I am in agreement with Dr. Judson C. Randolph (surgeon in chief,
Children's Hospital National Medical Center, Washington, D.C.) when he states,
"I think it is well within the guidelines of right and wrong to make
certain qualitative judgments about human life...." Dr. Randolph
continues: "If a severely
handicapped child were suddenly given one moment of omniscience and total
awareness of his or her outlook for the future, would that child necessarily
opt for life? No one has yet been able to demonstrate that the answer would
always be 'yes.' "4 In
judgment, the perspectives of the Christian tradition on life and its
meaning would suggest that in some instances the answer would be
"no." Our main task as reasonable persons is to discover where the
line is to be drawn and why. Our temptation as adults in a highly
function-oriented and comfort-biased world is to draw it in terms of adult
perspectives on comfort and functionability. What we are likely to forget--and
therefore what is eminently part of our responsibility for health--is that
these decisions are terribly anguishing, terribly risky, and utterly final.
Moral responsibility demands sensitivity to this and a corresponding humility.
4J. G. Randolph, "Ethical
Considerations in Surgery of the Newborn," Contemporary Surgery, 7 (1975), 17.
VI
In reflecting on "man's moral
responsibility for health," we may easily forget any number of things
about the notion of morality. The first thing we are tempted to forget is the
distinction between "moralism" and "morality." Moralism is
that attitude or mind-set that approaches human problems with a dominating,
perhaps even exclusive concern, for the prescriptive and proscriptive, for the
permissible and the nonpermissible, the do's and the don'ts. This is particularly the temptation of the Anglo-Saxon mind, which
thinks of law as being the answer to all problems, the only answer, and a fully
adequate answer. When this
attitude enters the realm of moral discourse and reflection, it becomes preoccupied
with norms and rules.
Now, there
is nothing objectionable about norms and rules-indeed, they are utterly
essential. But they are basically generalizations on the significance of human
conduct. If that is the case, our first
task is always to understand the significance of our conduct. It is only then
that we are positioned to formulate and apply norms. Preoccupation with norms is moralism, and the
problem with moralism is that it bypasses and therefore effectively subverts
the processes leading to understanding.
Without adequate understandings fully informed as possible by all the
disciplines that can enlighten the human-we fall into education by edict, which
is no education at all. And we fall into practice by conformity, which neglects
important human aspects of conduct. This hap-pens all too often in the area of
sexual morality, where our preoccupation with the rights and wrongs hurries us
over the very understanding that alone yields the true rights and wrongs.
In the
area of health care, there is, I submit, an enormous amount of moralizing going
on-a phenomenon that can block the development of a genuine morality, thus
subverting our moral responsibility for health care. For instance, the morality of care for the dying
is often popularly framed in terms of "pulling the plug" or "not
pulling the plug." We discuss whether there should be a law
controlling DNA recombinant research. We wonder whether a patient may elect to
forego hemodialysis. We ask whether the incompetent retarded person may be
protectively sterilized. We conduct long discussions about the moral propriety
of in vitro fertilization. And so on.
These are all important issues, of course. But their resolution must occur within a much broader
context if we are to avoid moralism, the context of profound deliberation
about human and Christian being and end, about who we are.
It is
conversation about who we are that is so often bypassed in contemporary
discussions about health care. But it is precisely who we are that will inform us about the shape of our health-care
responsibilities. (For a fuller treatment of those issues see Chapters 6 and
7.) For the moment, however, let me take but a single example. It is axiomatic
that we are social beings, that we move and literally have our being not as
atomized individuals, but as interrelated beings. We exist in relationships
and are dead without them. This is not surprising to those who believe that man
is created in the image and likeness of God, for the more we know of God, the
more we know that He is relation, that His very being is "being in and for
another." As man comes to know more about himself through psychiatry and
clinical psychology, it should not be surprising that his Godlikeness becomes
more obvious, that he sees that he is made for relational life, and that
everything in his makeup (including instincts and emotions) conspires to
relational possibility or, as undeveloped, hinders it.
The
ultimate meaning of this relational constitution of the human person is love.
In Christian perspective, we could put it as follows: The great commandment, in
a sense the only commandment, is the love of God and of neighbor for God's
sake. All other Christian duties are simply specifications of this command. But
not only is this a command; Cod's commands are also affirmations about
ourselves. In telling us that the great commandment is love of God and
neighbor, Christ was actually telling us what is good for us and what we are.
He was saying that our own completion and fulfillment are to be found here,
hence that ultimately our eternal happiness depends on love and is love. If one
is to find life, one must lose it-in the divestment of self that is love.
Now, what is interesting here is that
just as my ability to love God is His gift to me, so our ability to love each
other is our gift to each other. The greatest human need is to be loved; for
unloved, I remain unloving, withdrawn, self-encased. But when I am loved in a
full human way, selfhood, personal dignity, a feeling of security, a sense of
worth and dignity are conferred upon me-the very things that enable me to
respond to others as persons, to love them. Thus it is clear that because my
greatest fulfillment is the other-centeredness of love, my greatest human need
is for that which creates this possibility-that is, love from others, their
acceptance of me as a person. Similarly, my greatest
Some Neglected Aspects of Moral Responsibility for
Health 43 gift to them is my
self-donation to them7 because this is also their greatest need.
Modern psychology, in uncovering the growth process that leads to the ability
of self-donation in interpersonal relationships, has not only described a
capacity, it also has at once described a need. And in doing this it has
painted in bold colors the ultimate meaning of any concrete act of charity,
justice, fairness toward men.
What has all this to do with
responsibility for health care? The following, I would suggest: Unless
prevention, cure, and care are experienced as extensions of genuine human
caring and love, they are less than they could be. They do not touch the whole
person; rather, they minister to a body. They may heal a body, but we long for
and need a deeper healing from each other as the body is healed, or even at
times if it is to be healed. That is one good reason why persons of deep faith
and religious consecration should be in health care, for in our time, it is far
too easy for health care to be reduced to only bodily care, in a very
impersonal way. That is why there is a profound difference between physicians,
paramedical personnel, and a hospital with a self-image of vocation, on the
one hand, and those with a self-image of only "being in business" on
the other. This difference manifests itself in subtle but very important ways.
Unless we are aware of this, we drift toward moralism, the extension into the
moral sphere of a merely technological assessment of man.
What I am driving at is that moralism,
and excessive preoccupation with "problems" and the rights and
wrongs of omissions and commissions, too readily leads us to overlook the human
quality of care and cure-that which we need no matter what our condition. I
believe we are likely to forget this in discussing moral responsibility for
health. The New York Times recently
reported the remarks of a surgeon whose kidney-transplant recipient was
undergoing anxiety and depression after his transplant: "Well, I gave him
a good kidney; I can't help what's wrong with his brain."5
5New York Times (May 11,1977).